Categories
Aesthetics Relationships

Abang Adik Review: Getting Real About Fictional Feelings

{Spoilers Ahead!}

Image from South China Morning Post

“Bring tissues!” the director of Abang Adik (Jin Ong) winkingly forewarned in a promotional interview for the film. 

The throwaway succinctness of this remark, however, belies the full extent of the film’s artistic imperative. First, there are no two ways about its directorial intent: the audience is expected, given full permission and encouraged to cry their heart out. Second, since emotional engagement with the film is taken for granted, and the presence of tragedy within the story is already ‘spoiled’ at the outset, it signals that there is more to the film than being a tearjerker for its own sake. Crying may be instrumental to a proper appreciation of the film, but it is not its end goal.

A Tale of Abang and Adik: Interwoven Lives in an Isolating World

Abang Adik is centered on the fate and (mis)fortunes of the film’s eponymous ‘brothers’. Abang (Wu Kang-ren) and Adik (Jack Tan) are siblings not by consanguinity but circumstance. As undocumented Malaysia-born persons living on the margins, their found familial bond is forged from a shared sense of otherness and a desperate bid at normality. Abang tries his best to be the parental figure Adik seeks and needs, and Adik becomes the object of protection and affection that gives meaning to Abang’s life. Adik rebels— against the law, his socioeconomic condition and all forms of help; while Abang hopes— against Adik’s self-destruction and his own simple, self-sustained optimism.

We see Abang brandishing a wooden plank to shield Adik from would-be attackers (victims of Adik’s unlawful resort to earning quick money). Adik instinctively reaching out to embrace Abang after Abang suffers from a romantic misfortune. Abang and Adik cracking boiled eggs open with each other’s forehead as a wordless form of brotherly code. And finally, Abang and Adik giving in to their best and worst impulses in the catastrophic fallout set in motion by a split-second mistake at the film’s climax. These story beats are no doubt designed to emotionally provoke, and their efficacy is evident from the critical and audience acclaim the film has received.

Abang Adik review
Image from Bandar Aktiviti Seni

Abang Adik’s Emotional Enigma

I have initially found it puzzling that so much of the fanfare surrounding the film is focused on just how devastating the viewing experience is. What might be the reason behind Abang Adik’s strong emotional resonance with the Malaysian audience? 

Certainly, the film’s commentary on the unjust marginalization of stateless persons provides a sobering reminder of the harsh mundanity of their defenseless, disenfranchised lives. The familiar distinctiveness of a Malaysian setting (geographical, cultural and linguistic) enhances the film’s relatability. The actors are also fully convincing in their delivery of moving, naturalistic performances. And crucially, pulling all these elements together is a steady directorial hand that is prescient in its anticipation of the kinds of audience reaction that particular cinematic techniques will precipitate.

But I suspect that there is a deeper reason why the emotional reaction towards the film has become its most defining feature, and the answer might be this: Abang Adik’s blurring of the line between fiction and documentary meaningfully engages with what is known as ‘the paradox of fictional emotions’.

Briefly, the paradox raises the question of whether the emotional responses produced towards fictional characters can ever be genuine. In other words, if we know that these particular characters do not in fact exist, and these events and storylines did not in fact happen, then why do we consider the emotions that we feel towards them (not the lives they represent) to be real? 

Three main claims are commonly raised in relation to this paradox: 

  1. we often have emotional responses to fictional characters that seem genuine;
  2. we do not actually believe that these fictional characters/ events exist/ happen; and 
  3. emotions are only genuine and rational if we believe the situation giving rise to them is real.

These three claims cannot simultaneously be true, thus giving rise to the paradox.

Philosophers have responded to these claims in a variety of ways:

  • In relation to (a), some argue that while it is natural and fitting for us to have these emotional responses, these responses are nevertheless incoherent (they make no sense), incorrect (they are wrong or mistaken since the target object of the emotion does not actually exist), or are simply a make-believe (they are “quasi” emotions, i.e. they are not emotions in the full and proper sense). 
  • In relation to (b), it has been argued that we may believe those emotions to be genuine because our perceptual capacities visually perceive fictional objects to be real; though this view has been rejected on the basis that the very knowledge that we are encountering a fictional object will already make us perceive it differently from a real-life object.
  • On the other hand, (c) has been negated either on the ground that emotions do not involve ‘thinking’ and thus the status of its target object does not matter; or that fictional emotions can indeed be genuine, to the extent that they are comparable to simulated emotions that arise when we create imaginary counterfactuals whilst engaging in practical reasoning to solve real-life problems. 

My take on Abang Adik is this. We find the emotional aspect of Abang Adik compelling and worthy of repeated highlight because it presents to us a puzzle: the fact that Abang Adik’s world of fiction closely mirrors what happens in real life puts the audience in an emotional double-bind where the paradox is concerned. That is, a conclusion that fictional emotions are genuine puts us in an equally morally uncomfortable position as the conclusion that fictional emotions are not real.

A quick survey of the audience reaction towards Abang Adik (see images below) reveals that the audience prides itself in having felt empathy and sympathy for Abang and Adik’s predicament, possibly because this signifies that we possess morally right– and, dare I say, righteous– convictions. If we feel Adik’s helpless anguish when he meets Abang for the last time before Abang is executed, it must mean that we are good people with the ability to understand the plight of those more unfortunate than us! Such a moral high ground may not seem as earned, say, when we feel Rose’s grief as she reluctantly lets go of Jack in order to be rescued at the end of Titanic.


If Fictional Emotions were Real 

If fictional emotions were genuine, and if attributing full genuine status to fictional emotions meant equating emotions towards fictional characters with emotions towards real-life people, then we might find ourselves confronted with some thorny ethical dilemmas. 

First, would such an equation inadvertently diminish the moral status of these real-life people? Is it not distasteful, and rather absurd, to say that the empathy we feel for deaf-mute Abang’s augmented sense of isolation is as ‘real’ as that for a real-life disabled, stateless person? 

Second, since the characters of Abang and Adik clearly do not exist in reality and thus nothing can actually be done for their characters, will we end up settling for a ‘feel-good’ moral complacency that stops short of converting these feelings into real action?

Take, for example, Adik’s patent anger and discomfort at having to reach out to his estranged father in order to have the latter vouch for Adik’s Malaysia-born status– an act essential to Adik’s ability to obtain an identity card. We might feel deeply indignant that Adik is being forced to ask for help from a father who has chosen to abandon him at a young age, just so that Adik would be able to create a future for himself. We might nevertheless conclude (quite rightly) that there is nothing to be done for Adik’s character since Adik is not a real person. Yet, since empathy is not that easily transferred from a fictional character to a real person, we might also end up doing nothing to help real-life people encountering the same problem.

Abang Adik review
Image from Ming Pao
Perhaps a survey can be conducted to find out how many of the film’s audience who take these feelings very seriously manage to replicate them for Adik’s real-life counterpart, and then do something about it.

“Go find your father and get your IC.” – Abang
“I don’t have a father. All I have is you.” – Adik

Abang Adik, 2023

If Fictional Emotions were Not Real 

If fictional emotions turned out to be not real, and thus less is ‘at stake’ so to speak, we are confronted with a slightly different set of dilemmas. Most notably, this awareness may produce an aesthetic distance that leads us to disproportionately empathize and sympathize with morally questionable characters.

For instance, the ‘safety’ provided by the ‘not real’ nature of our emotions towards Adik makes it easier for us to see him as a character deserving of our pity and compassion, even if we have seen him engaging in exploitative behavior (towards illegal migrants even more helpless than himself) and violent actions (towards the selfless social worker, Jia En (Serene Lim)). Adik’s status as one of the film’s titular protagonists makes us want to root for him, at times to the detriment of the other supporting characters. But in the real world, we might not find it so convenient to overlook his transgressions even if we do understand his misguided motivations, and thus we might be sterner in determining the limit of the ‘emotional just deserts’ that Adik should receive. 

Additionally, when the significance of fictional emotions is minimized or deemed inconsequential, we might also be more willing to revel in what Samuel Johnson terms “the delight of tragedy”. Put differently, we might find it more palatable to “fancy ourselves unhappy for a moment” and thus succumb to a voyeurism of suffering when we are aware of the fictionality of a situation. Just like virtue-signaling celebrities who partake in feel-good philanthropic tourism, when we ‘indulge’ ourselves in the misery experienced by Abang and Adik during the movie’s 115-minute runtime and thereafter give ourselves a pat in the back, we are effectively taking a vicarious tour of the misfortunes of the real-life people Abang and Adik are meant to represent. In short, our empathy is rendered recreational.

I always wonder why I was born here. I don’t have a home. I don’t even have parents. I can only watch from afar. – Abang

Abang Adik, 2023

Notice that the existence of the paradox does not preclude the ability to enjoy and appreciate  fiction. The status of fictional emotions as genuine or otherwise might predispose us to adopt a certain mindset towards the moral insights and moral actions which can be generated from those feelings, but it does not by itself give rise to any normative implications. The paradox is useful, not because it provides prescriptions about what we must do with these fictional feelings, but because it prods us to think carefully about what these fictional feelings can(not) do. 

Abang Adik review
Image from South China Morning Post

Abang Adik Review: Concluding Thoughts

Herein lies the genius of Abang Adik: the film intrigues, not just because it inspires by weaving the socio-political with the personal in bold and creative ways, but more importantly because it discombobulates. In consciously enlisting the audience’s emotional repertoire to convey its core message about human connection and love, the film inevitably ropes us into a conversation about the relationship between fiction, emotions and real life.

We leave the cinema weighed down by the bleakness of the film’s subject matter, secretly relieved that we can take an emotional break and ‘come back to’ our actual lives; yet we cannot help but be discomfited by the realization that what we have just felt– whether or not we think it to be genuine– would very much be real somewhere, and to someone, beyond the cinematic walls. 

Categories
Relationships Society

Pandemic Social Responsibility: Why Bother Caring About Others During the Pandemic?

The COVID-19 pandemic brings out many issues that have been swept under the rug or have been assumed to be settled once and for all. In particular, we see the extraordinary extent of individual liberty that people claim they have. 

No Mask
Pew Research Centre

“I am free to do whatever I want; I am free not to wear a mask and not to get the vaccine” is the form of argument that we often see. 

I was (and still am) appalled by some people’s stubbornness to not wear a mask but my initial reason for having this response mainly came from my upbringing and not necessarily for more philosophical reasons. My family and the society that I grew up in have always taught me to think about others or to think about the benefits of society as a whole. Even though I align myself with this value, the pandemic made me realize that I did not think more critically about why I should think about others. 

No Pandemic Social Responsibility: Anti-Maskers and Anti-Vaxxers

It is when I observed anti-maskers’ and anti-vaxxers’ arguments that forced my brain to do some thinking about it. 

The presence of these people shows that not everybody feels the same duty to think about others and I think it is understandable to a certain degree. Nobody is expected to be good but it would be nice if you are good. Nobody is expected to be altruistic but it would be nice if you are altruistic. 

Even though some people might pull in religious commandments or objective moral values (that there are things that are intrinsically good and wrong) to justify altruism, not everybody subscribes to religions or moral objectivism.

For example, if we say that thinking about others is good because God loves or demands it or because it is simply good, I do not think this will move the seculars or moral subjectivists (the opposite of moral objectivists) that much.

They could ask us back: “But why–without using God or objective moral values–is it good to think about others? And even if you show me that it’s good, that does not mean that I should do it.” Therefore, it is arguably quite difficult to convince everybody why they should–if not must–care about other people. Conversely, it can be quite difficult to explain to somebody why we should think about others.

Thomas Hobbes’ State of Nature and Social Contract

Thomas Hobbes State of Nature
Discourses on Minerva

As I think of an answer (if I ever have to confront an anti-masker or an anti-vaxxer), two people came to my mind: Thomas Hobbes and John Stuart Mill, both classic philosophers and political theorists from England. Hobbes argues that, before any form of civilization or society was formed, humans were in a state of nature that was akin to a state of war. In this state, there are no laws and everybody is free to do anything to preserve her own well-being and life. 

This freedom includes killing others and exhausting resources as much as possible for one’s own benefit. While the infinite amount of freedom that one has seems heaven-like, Hobbes claims that the opposite is true, which is why he calls it the state of war. During this state, people cannot live in peace and they always have to be on the edge because anyone can kill them and take their food and shelter. It is an ugly fight for survival all the time and Hobbes famously describes this life as “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” (This is perhaps Hobbes’s most quoted phrase) Therefore, in order to get out of this miserable state and still preserve one’s own life and resources, society is formed

A society consists of people who agree to obey a set of rules or values for the mutual benefits of every member of the society. In other words, every member of the society agrees to forgo some amount of her infinite freedom in exchange for the security of her life and resources.

This agreement is commonly known as the social contract. One now has the right to life and the right to property possession. Killing and stealing then become terms that we use and assign negative connotations such as ‘wrongness’ or ‘badness’ to. This is different from pre-society or state of nature, where it is simply either ‘taking someone’s life’ or ‘taking unguarded resources,’ and it is neither right nor wrong. 

The COVID-19 pandemic brings out many issues that have been swept under the rug or have been assumed to be settled once and for all. In particular, we see the extraordinary extent of individual liberty that people claim they have. 

A society consists of people who agree to obey a set of rules or values for the mutual benefits of every member of the society. In other words, every member of the society agrees to forgo some amount of her infinite freedom in exchange for the security of her life and resources.

This agreement is commonly known as the social contract. One now has the right to life and the right to property possession. Killing and stealing then become terms that we use and assign negative connotations such as ‘wrongness’ or ‘badness’ to. This is different from pre-society or state of nature, where it is simply either ‘taking someone’s life’ or ‘taking unguarded resources,’ and it is neither right nor wrong. 

Before we move on to John Stuart Mill, we have to first know the general stances of the political philosophers at the time. Hobbes’s ultimate goal is to show that living in a society, especially one that is under an absolute ruler (a monarch, for example), is much better than living a nasty, brutish, and short life in the state of nature a.k.a the state of war. Other philosophers like John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau agree with Hobbes about the brutality of the state of nature but argue that a democratic government should be preferred instead. 

John Struat Mill on the Limits of Governmental Control and Harm Principle

Compared to the others, Mill has a different point to say.

He believes that no matter which government we are under, monarchy or democracy (or other forms of governments), our freedom can still be threatened by either the tyranny of the monarch or the tyranny of the majority (i.e., when the decision of the majority oppresses the minority, which can be very bad if the minority is actually right).

He proposes that there must be limits to the control that the government has over the citizens because they have their individual freedom to live their lives however they want. 

Mill Harm Principle
Thinking Prismatically

But here’s the catch. This freedom should always be granted to the individual as long as the individual does not harm other people, which is known as the “harm principle.”

Mill writes, “the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.” An individual’s act (and freedom) can be rightfully restricted if her act is harming other people. I believe many of us live by this principle that it does not seem that strange. We usually let one be if she does not harm other people, despite how unusual her acts may be. We practise this principle all the time. 

Why Pandemic Social Responsibility Is So Important: Combining Hobbes and Mill’s Views

Despite the universality of Mill’s harm principle, we see that some people fought for the right to not wear a mask (excluding people who have breathing difficulties) without thinking that their interest not only harms their lives but also that it harms the right for other people to live, which is a bigger deal than the right to not breathe under a mask.

They cannot then complain that their individual freedom is not respected. Moreover, they fail to see that the more fundamental reason why they could even live to fight for their rights in the first place–their existence–should be attributed to the fact that other people limited their infinite freedom such that we all do not live in the state of war anymore as described by Hobbes.

It is through others’ willingness to sacrifice some part of their freedom that we exist and it is through our sacrifice that they too can exist.

If we do not consider the good of society as a whole and we harm others, then we should not expect ourselves to remain in the society and have our freedom to be equally respected.

Thus, if you have to deal with somebody (who does not believe in objective moral values, in particular) that claims that they have no responsibility to think about others and that they have the individual freedom to do anything, including harming others, remind them if they really do and how they can exist in the first place to argue with you. It may sound like a threat but all it really is is a short overview of the social contract and the limits of individual freedom. *peace out*

Categories
Relationships

A Philosophical Guide to Friendship: 3 Types of Friendships and Which Should You Keep?

“Friendship always benefits; love sometimes injures.”

Seneca

“A friend is, as it were, a second self.”

Cicero

In our daily lives, it would be unthinkable to most people to not have friends. Friendship is an essential part of our lives – the memories we shared with our childhood friends, the joy of reminiscing about our school days with a long-time  friend, or even the hardships we go through with our work colleagues. All these are experiences that make life worth living. Furthermore, friends are there when we need help. They help us through rough patches, just as we do the same for them. We share new hobbies, laugh at the same movies and enrich each other’s lives. 

So, what does philosophy say about friendship? As it happens, plenty. While it is not the most prevalent topic, friendship has its place especially among ancient philosophers. 

Aristotle and Seneca on Friendship – Which Friendships Do You Have?

In Book VIII of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle categorised friendship into three sorts: friendship of pleasure, that of utility and virtue. Of these three, Aristotle hailed the friendship of virtue as the friendship that is most desired – one that is essential to achieving Eudaimonia (a good life).

Type of Friendship #1: Friendship of Pleasure

Friendship

Friendship of pleasure is understood as a type of friendship formed due to the pleasure you gain from being with someone. By pleasure, it does not mean the pleasure of the flesh. For instance, you make friends with someone whom you met at a party where you guys had a smashing time together. 

Type of Friendship #2: Friendship of Utility

Friendship

Next is Friendship of utility. Here we are referring to something more material – we are friends with someone  because of the utility we gain in a relationship. For instance, we become friends with someone who is generous with his or her  wealth, or someone who has helped us in the past. We can go even further and categorise this friendship as a quid pro quo relationship, stating that this friendship is only sustained by the material trade between two parties.

Type of Friendship #3: Friendship of Virtue

Friendship

Yet, to Aristotle, the strongest bond resides within the friendship of virtue.

Aristotle believes this type of friendship would allow both parties to grow, and eventually achieve eudaimonia.

In friendship of virtue, a friendship is built upon the values of both parties. This is not to say that friendships of pleasure and utility are unworthy, but they are formed on the basis of things we can gain from the other party.

In virtuous friendship, two parties  become friends due to the virtuous characteristics they have in common, such as being kind, courageous, morally upright or wise. They may share common values on topics of importance, such as politics, faith or ethics. While they might not always share the same viewpoints, they do not try to win one another over. Instead, they discuss their ideas, striving to enhance understanding of each other. They trust each other with our deepest secrets, and expose themselves fully to each other.

Neither of either parties is superior over the other – they are of equal standing, striving to build a good life with each other in mind. In short, in a virtuous friendship, two parties try to  bring the best out of each other. 

“The wise man, I say, self-sufficient though he be, nevertheless desires friends if only for the purpose of practising friendship, in order that his noble qualities may not lie dormant”

Seneca, Letters to Lucillius, Letter 35

Expanding further by injecting a Stoic flavour to this essay, Seneca’s views are similar to that of Aristotle. A wise stoic is self-sufficient on his own, nevertheless he seeks out friendships, as that is a basic human craving. However, he does not seek friendship solely for his own sake. Rather, he seeks out friendship so that he can practice his virtues, and “that he may have someone by whose sick-bed he himself may sit, someone a prisoner in hostile hands whom he himself may set free. He who regards himself only, and enters upon friendships for this reason, reckons wrongly.” (Letters 9) 

How to be a good friend to someone?

1. Re-examine your existing friendships.

How to Choose Friends
Pexels

Firstly, we should start by re-examining all our existing friendships.

Examine the positions of both you and your friend – are the both of you equal in this relationship? What is the key element that holds this friendship together? Is it due to benefits (work colleagues) or pleasure (the other person is a cool dude)? Will that friendship be over if the element of benefit or pleasure is taken away from the equation?  Is there a possibility to grow into something more? How would you define “something more”? Is it based on intimacy? Common hobbies? Or as Aristotle put it, virtue?

2. Self-improvement

Self Improvement
Pexels

Next, improve yourself.

If our goal is to improve the quality of our friendship, the first place to start would be ourselves. Improving ourselves should be the main priority in the quest for a true friendship – so that we are able to offer more to our friends, and be the sort of person that one might wish to know in order to better themselves.

“Try to perfect yourself, if for no other reason, in order that you may learn how to love.”

Seneca, Letter to Lucilius, Letter 35

3. Examine Your Role in Each Friendships

How to Choose Friends

Finally, examine our role in each of our friendships.

What is our role in a friendship of utility?  What sort of benefits are we giving to our friends? If it is of pleasure, what sort of pleasures are we providing? Do we share some sort of common interest with them, so that we are fun to hang out with? Maybe we are funny, and people come to us for laughs and to feel comfortable? Finally, do we have any friendships of virtue? Are we the sort of person that might be viewed as a person of virtue, that we might inspire our friends to do great things, and they are friends with us because they think that we are friends worthy to be, just because we are ourselves?

What Types of Friendships Should You Choose or Keep?

So, what happens after we gain knowledge of the types of friendships and relook into our existing friendships?

Should we eschew friendships of pleasure and utility now?

No, instead, we should aim to grow to be more reliant on ourselves, and focus on the aspect of give rather than take. “But,” I hear you say, “shouldn’t we expect our friends to be of a higher standard as well? If we are so focused on giving, won’t we be tired?”

Viewed from a Stoic lens, this sentence itself comes close to being absurd. As a stoic, we are self-sufficient – we do not require friends to make us happy. Friends are there so we can practice our virtuous qualities, and that we may learn to give more than take. 

In short, as much as we want friends who accept us for who we are, and at the same time encourage us to be better as a person, we should also work towards strengthening the different types of friendships we have, thereby creating more meaningful connections in this very disconnected world.

Everyone is constantly finding the key to a truer friendship, whatever that means. This article is meant to introduce you, the reader, to some of the ideas of friendship in philosophy and to illustrate one point in philosophy: 

Nothing is too small a matter for philosophy. Good luck in your journey of seeking for and building meaningful friendships.